Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция


НазваниеФилософское антиковедение и классическая традиция
страница2/22
ТипДокументы
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   ...   22

I

Marinus tells the story about Proclus’ successful prayer to Asclepius, resulted in a miraculous recovery of one Asclepigeneia, “the wife of Theagenes our benefactor” (Marinus, Vita Procli 29, p. 35, 18–39 Saffrey–Segonds; transl. by M. Edwards):

Taken with him the great Pericles of Lydia, a man who was himself no mean philosopher, Proclus visited the shrine of the god to pray on behalf of the invalid. For at that time the city still enjoyed the use of this and retained intact the temple of the Savior. And while he was praying in the ancient manner, a sudden change was seen in the maiden and a sudden recovery occurred, for the Savior, being a god, healed her easily… Such was the act he performed, yet in this as in every other case he evaded the notice of the mob, and offered no pretext to those who wished to plot against him.

The house in which he dwelt was in this respect of great assistance to him. For in addition to the rest of his good fortune, his dwelling too was extremely congenial to him, being also the one inhabited by his ‘father’ Syrianus and by Plutarch, whom he himself styled his ‘forefather’.

Then he briefly describes its location as follows:

…γείτονα μὲν οὖσαν τοῦ ἀπὸ Σοφοκλέους ἐπιφανοῦς Ἀσκληπιείου καὶ τοῦ πρὸς τῷ θεάτρῳ Διονυσίου, ὁρωμένην δὲ ἢ καὶ ἄλλως αἰσθητὴν γιγνομένην τῇ ἀκροπόλει τῆς Ἀθηνᾶς.

Apparently he chooses the surrounding religious constructions as the appropriate landmarks and states, that “…it was a neighbor to the shrine of Asclepius celebrated by Sophocles, and [the shrine] of Dionysius by the theatre…” This is understandable since the purpose of Marinus is to emphasize Proclus’ intimate relations with the deities, especially Athena and Asclepius.

But what the last clause is about? Rosán (1949, 30) renders it thus: “…it could be seen or otherwise perceived from the Acropolis of Athena.”

Frantz (1988, 43) thinks that Marinus wanted to say by this phrase that the house “…could be seen, or at least discerned, by someone standing on the Acropolis of Athena”, writing that “Professor Harold Cherniss, who kindly looked at the passage with me, suggested that the dative, unless it is simply bad grammar, is used to emphasize the fact that the viewer is standing on the Acropolis. ‘Or at least discerned’ limits the preceding ‘visible’, rather then offering a senseless alternative ‘otherwise perceived’ (Rosán’s translation), and implies that someone standing on the Acropolis could see it with some difficulty. Homer Thompson, who happened to be in Athens at the time the problem arose, responded to a query whether the facts justified this interpretation with the following: ‘Looking over the present top of the south wall of the Acropolis one has no difficulty in seeing the supposed site of the house; but in Late Antiquity one would presumably have had to climb up to a sentry walk’” (1988, 43, n. 169).

In his review of the above Castrén (1991, 475) takes this to mean that “the House of Proclus was visible from the Acropolis and also otherwise somehow manifest, obviously because of the considerable bulk of construction immediately below the eyes of the spectator”.0

More recently M. Edwards (2000, 104, n. 329) suggested it to mean that the house became visible from the acropolis only when the shrine of Asclepius was destroyed (“seen, or if not it became visible, from the acropolis of Athena”). The idea is attractive because it could be used for indirect dating of the temple’s destruction. But should this really be the case, why did Marinus, having mentioned the demolishing of the temple a few lines before the passage in question, not simply state this? We still therefore incline to take it to mean that “someone standing on the Acropolis could see the house with some difficulty.”0

A Plan of Athens in the 5th century C. E.0
What is intriguing is that a large building complex on the southern slope of the Acropolis, located between the Odeum of Herodes Atticus and the Theater of Dionysus, and therefore approximately matching this description, was actually excavated in 1955. Unfortunately, the work was accomplished only partially and under extreme pressure of time, before the Dionysiou Areopagiou Street was constructed over the site (Meliades 1955).

According to Dontas (1956) the building in its final form was constructed in the period between the end of the fourth and the beginning the fifth century C. E. Only the northern part of the area was excavated because “the rest expands under the area occupied by modern houses, in the back-yards of which could be observed its traces and floor-mosaics” (his article in: Ergon tes Archaiologikes Etaireias kata to 1955 (Athena) 5–14, quoted in Oikonomides 1977: 11–12).

Above: the Dionysiou Areopagiou Street, present view (photographed by the authors in 2009); below: the area in the period of excavation in 1955 (after Frantz 1988)

“This was no ordinary house by Athenian standards, – writes Frantz (1988, 43). – A large room opens into a wide apse (6.60 m. wide, 4.40 m. deep); the lower part of the wall of the apse was surfaced with marble revetment slabs. Above the revetment the thickness of the wall diminishes, and in it were seven niches suitable for sculpture (as in the Areopagus houses). The floors of both parts of the room were covered with mosaics in elaborate geometric patterns, the apse being emphasized by having the floor laid at a slightly higher level. Against the outer face of the east wall of the apse was a small shrine of Cybele, identified by a statuette of the goddess in a niche in the wall. A statue base with a funerary relief carved on the front served as an offering table. Both pieces of sculpture were re-used in these positions…”

The excavators were the first to suggest that the building (now labeled as House Chi) can be identified with the one owned by Plutarch’s family and associated with the names of the founder of the Athenian school of Neoplatonism and his most close associates, Syrianus and Proclus. Indeed, in addition to an obvious fact that it perfectly matches Marinus’ description, it clearly belongs to the type of buildings used in Antiquity, as Frantz put it, “for the gathering of audiences and accommodating lectures and called generally ‘philosophical schools’.” It is equally important that the building seems to be used continuously during the fifth century, but was abandoned in the sixth century C.E. The hypothesis has now been materialized in the form of a memorial plate hung in situ.0

The identification is also confirmed by the reach finds (artistic works and an inscription), illustrating religious and intellectual interests of its inhabitants. Apart of the shrine of Cybele and various religious objects (even a sacrificial knife in the neck of the piglet!), and numerous objects of everyday use (lamps, vases, etc), in the building and its close vicinity there had been discovered numerous statues of the gods (including a statue of Isis), a portrait, tentatively identified as this of a philosopher; and an inscription with the words σοφίης and βίοτον. The head of a philosopher (some speculate – this of Plutarch) dated to the fifth century is also said to come from the vicinity.0

II

According to Agathias Scholasticus (On the Reign of Justinian, 2.30.3) the last head of the Academy Damascius (c. 458–after 538) had managed to revitalize the school and to assemble in Athens the best philosophers ‘from all over the domain of Hellenism.’ But the philosophers had already been driven from the ‘House of Proclus’ by Plutarch’s relatives (the legal owners of the building) and the house itself was extensively rebuild or even abandoned (Karivieri 1994), so he had to find another location for his school.0 An attractive hypothesis, now widely accepted, is this by P. Athanassiadi who suggested that he may well have established his school “in a superb building complex on the northern slope of the Areopagus, which must have functioned for many years as living quarters, as a teaching and research center, and as a place of worship” (Athanassiadi 1999, 47; Appendix I; PhH 145 and 151E with footnotes).

Look at the plan of Athens above: the Areopagus Houses A, B and C are found between the Areopagus and the Forum (the Roman Agora). Frantz (1988, 38) describes their location and major features as follows:

“The four buildings constituting the Areopagus group stood on the lower slopes of the hill, on terraces leveled for their predecessors. Their sitting and plans were conditioned by the two east-west streets that ran through the area and by the terrain itself. The northernmost, House A, was contiguous to the South Road, which forms the southern boundary of the Agora, but with a very slight difference in orientation so that its northwest corner encroaches on the road by about a meter. House B is about 15 meters to the southeast, a little farther up the hill; the eastern half was built against the remaining wall of the Upper South Road. House C lies still farther up the slope, directly across the road from House B. The south edge of the road therefore determined the line of its northern wall while a scrap in the hard rock of the Areopagus limited further expansion to the south. Of House D only the apse remains ca. 35 meters west of House C…”

The northern slope of Areopagus was inhabited from the classical times, and the houses were constantly rebuilt. Constructions visible now are mainly dated to the period after the Herulian attack at 267 C.E. and up to the sixth century. An example of longevity is a construction on the slope of Areopagus, west of House A, which was built in the fifth century B.E.C. and still occupied in the fifth century C. E. A few small marble figures were found here, including a statuette of Asclepius, a head of Sarapis, and a statuette of Tyche (Frantz 1988, 36ff).

A large central hall – the common feature of all the Areopagus houses as well as the House of Proclus (House Chi) – clearly indicates that the buildings served some public purposes. The halls and adjacent peristyle courts are admittedly perfect places for educational or religious gatherings, conducted privately. The chambers that surround the central hall could be used as “seminar rooms”, some sort of cabinets or private dwellings. At any rate, a building of this type, too spacious for private quarters and not suitable for official use could suite well for hosting a private educational institution.

A perfect example of a similar type is relatively recently uncovered in Aphrodisias. It is the so-called North Temenos House – a large building complex located near the temple of Aphrodite on the edges of the city-center (cf. a picture below). This spacious construction with large apsidal halls and other rooms suitable for public use resembles the Areopagus houses in many ways and could also host a philosophical school.0 The houses feature elaborate mosaic pavements and were adorned with sculpture. Some perfect specimens produced locally, including the marble paneling that decorated the walls, and a number of plaster capitals carved with Aphrodite, Eros and similar images, were found during the excavation and can now be seen in the museum. The houses were abandoned after the seventh centuries’ earthquake.

The historians of ancient philosophy are visiting the ‘House of Damascius’.

March 2009, a conference “Iamblichus: his sources and influence”

(organized by The Irish Institute of Hellenic Studies at Athens and

the Centre for Ancient philosophy and the Classical tradition,

Novosibirsk University, Russia)


House C, Nymphaeum; above: its present condition;

below: its state in the time of excavation in the 1970s (after Frantz 1988)
“The most important feature of House C is a nymphaeum leading down from the southeast corner of the central peristyle by two marble steps flanked by marble columns to a small triclinium (ca. 3 x 3.50 m.). On its east side this looked into an apsidal room housing a semicircular pool… The motivation for this construction was obviously the ready availability of water from a fine fountain house into which the water from a spring higher up the hill had been channeled since the second or third century…” (Frantz 1988, 38)

A part of a large building complex in Aphrodisias, North Temenos House,

which is labeled by the researchers as the school of philosophy residence

Various sculptures, some in an excellent state of preservation, were found hidden in wells0 and in the destruction debris over and around houses. The most important are those found in two wells in House C. Some sculptures, like a superb head of Nike or a portrait bust of Antoninus Pius (both are on display in the Agora museum; S 2354 and S 2436), are more or less conventional, while the others, like small statues of Herakles and Hermes, heads of Nemesis and Helios, a statuette of a seated philosopher, and statuettes of Tyche, Serapis and Asclepius (S 871, 885, 875, etc.) represent religious and intellectual preferences of the Last Hellenes rather well.0

Reflecting the syncretic religious situation of the Late Antiquity, the houses on the north slope of Areopagus seem to be literally surrounded by various public and private places of worship. For instance, three large blocks of Egyptian granite and an engraved bronze disk with Egyptian motives, found on the hillside, could indicate that a shrine of Isis was located somewhere in the area; a Mithraeum could stay nearby, since two pieces of sculpture, associated with Mithras are discovered in the vicinity; and a head of Selene in relief, which could be somehow related with a shrine dedicated to Hecate or Cybele, was found in a well down the hill (Frantz 1988, 37).

Bronze Disk, Agora Museum B 904, drawn after Frantz 1988

We do not know what happened to the buildings after 529, when the Academy was closed and its members immigrated to Persia.0 Quite probably that afterwards the building continued to be used as a school, since in the seventh century it was still possible to study philosophy in Athens, as did Theodorus of Tarsus, before becoming Archbishop of Canterbury in 669 (Frantz et al. 1988, 33, n. 120; DOP 19, 1965).
III

We will conclude with a note on blood sacrifices. The most intriguing discovery in this respect is a grave of a year-old piglet, found in the ‘House of Proclus.’ For some purpose the sacrificial knife was left in the neck of the victim and the grave was filled with other offerings, such as a lamp with a running Eros on the disk and vases. The find is variously interpreted by the scholars. It could simply be related to the Roman ceremony of Terminalia (a ritualized setting boundary to the building). Also in the Roman context it could be an offering to the local genii on the occasion of, say, an important event or a save return from a long journey. But it could well be a part of a rite dedicated to the Mother of the Gods, performed privately (or even secretly!), since an appropriate shrine is found in the house and, according to Marinus, the Neo-Platonists worshipped the Mother of the Gods in her various hypostases (cf. Vita Procli 19). The blood of an animal was also a proper offering to the moon-goddess or Hecate,0 while according to Julian’ Oratio 5.177B–C a pig could be an appropriate offering for the gods of the underworld.

The House of Proclus: the famous ‘piglet grave’ (after Frantz 1988)

Our narrative source could perhaps elucidate this last point. Although no instance of a piglet (or any other animal) sacrifice is recorded, Marinus inform us that Proclus personally experienced “the fiery apparitions of Hecate” (having learned the rituals from Plutarch’s daughter Asclepigeneia)0 and

…actually caused rains by an apposite use of a iunx (ἴυγγά τινα), releasing Attica from a baneful drought. He also laid down defenses against earthquakes, and tested the power of the prophetic tripod, and produced verses on its decline (Marinus, Vita Procli 28, p. 33, 19–26 Saffrey–Segonds; transl. by M. Edwards)

Marinus mentions other sacrifices practiced in the Neoplatonic school, and constantly emphasizes Proclus’ intimate relations with the gods, especially Asclepius and the female generative principle, which extends from the Moon to Hecate and Cybele.0

The Iunx (ἴυγξ, wryneck) is a bird (in mythology, a daughter of Pan and Echo) which has long been associated with love spells in magic. In order to influence an unfaithful lover the sorcerer would catch a wryneck, fix her to a wheel and rotate.0 Later the term iunx and the magical procedures associated with it underwent some evolution. In the domain of love magic it started to designate an appropriate instrument – the wheel – itself, while in the Platonic tradition it was understood symbolically as Erotic binding force which links men to the gods. This interpretation is most famously found in the Chaldean Oracles, where the iunges (‘the magic wheels of Hecate,’ fr. 206 Des Places) are identified with the ideas (or thoughts) of the highest divine entity, the Father, while Eros (‘the first to leap from the Paternal Intellect,’ fr. 42 Des Places) is understood as a cosmic force which binds the worlds together and harmonizes the universe with the soul. The iunges, the lowest entities in the chain of being, acting as messengers and constantly moving from the Father to the material world, help the theurgist to connect the Primordial Triad of the Chaldeans with the rest of beings. Besides, the iunges are associated with some planetary forces, the ‘Intellectual pillars’ which support an ordered movement of the planets. The iunges, invoked by a theurgist, were though to move physically to an appropriate planetary sphere and to provide a contact with the material world (fr. 77–79 Des Places).0

Rotating the wheel in the process of a theurgic rite, the sorcerer receives certain magical ‘names’ (fr. 87 Des Places), also called iunges (the divine messengers therefore are symbolically identified with the messages they brought from above). An Oracle states that the names, pronounced by those who understand the divine utterance, reveal to the theurgist their extraordinary powers (cf. fr. 150 Des Places).

Now according to Marinus, Proclus from time to time busied himself with practical religion, usually upon other people’s request. His prayer “in the ancient manner” to Asclepius helped a woman to recover, and certain rites saved Attica from a drought and earthquake (Vita Procli 28–29, quoted above; cf. 17). One may notice that in both cases the goals were quite practical and the ways they were achieved resemble magic rather than theurgy. We cannot be sure from the text whether Proclus performed the rites in a physical or a symbolic manner, but the instance of piglet’s sacrifice definitely suggests that the real animal sacrifices were normal for the period and could be a part of the religious practice of the Neoplatonic school. Marinus seems to confirm this, saying that Proclus, otherwise a strict vegetarian, ate meat ‘for the sake of a rite’ (Vita Procli 12 and 19). It is quite possible therefore that in order to influence weather the Neoplatonic philosopher “in the ancient manner” had used a real bird rather than a clever planetary device of a sort described by Psellus as “a sphere embedded with sapphire and swung around by means of a leather strap” (PG 122.1133 A 8–9; Majercik 1989, 30).

References

Athanassiadi, P., ed., tr. (1999) Damascius. The Philosophical History. Athens.

Cameron, A. (1969) “The Last Days of the Academy in Athens,” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, n.s. 15, 7–29.

Camp, John McK. II (1994) The Athenian Agora. A Guide to the Excavation and Museum. Athens.

Castrén, P., ed. (1994) Post-Herulian Athens. Aspects of Live and Culture in Athens, A. D. 267 –529. Helsinki.

Dillon, J. M. (2007) “The Religion of the Last Hellenes”, Rites et croyances dans les religions du monde romain: huit exposés suivis de discussions. Genève: Fondation Hardt: 117–147.

Edwards, M. J., tr. (2000) Neoplatonic Saints. The Lives of Plotinus and Proclus by their Students. Liverpool.

Erim, K. T. (1989) Aphrodisias. A Guide to the Site and its Museum. Istanbul.

Frantz, A., Tompson, H., Travlos, J. (1988) The Athenian Agora. Results of Excavations conducted by the Americal School of Classical Studies at Athens. Vol. XXIV: Late Antiquity, A. D. 267–700. Princeton, N. J.; reviewed by P. Castrén in: Gnomon 63 (1991) 474–476.

Hällström, G. af. (1994) “The Closing of the Neoplatonic School in A. D. 529: An Additional Aspect,” Castrén 1994, 140–159.

Jones, A. (1999) “The Horoscope of Proclus,” Classical Philology 94, 81–88.

Karivieri, A. (1994) “The ‘House of Proclus’ on the Southern Slope of the Acropolis. A Contribution,” Castrén 1994, 115–140.

Majercik, R., tr. (1989) The Chaldean Oracles. Leiden.

Meliades, J. (1955) “Ἀνασκαφαὶ νοτίως τῆς Ἀκροπόλεως”, ΠΑΑΗ (1955) [1960] 36–52.

Oikonomides, Al. N., tr. (1977) Marinos of Neapolis. The Extant Works, or The Life of Proclus and the Commentary on the Dedomena of Euclid. Greek Text with facing (English or French) Translation, Testimonia De vita Marini, an Introduction and Bibliography. Chicago.

Rosán, L. J. (1949) The Philosophy of Proclus. The Final Stage of Ancient Though. New York.

Saffrey, H. D., Segonds, A.-P., eds. (2001) Proclus ou Sur le bonheur, avec la collaboration de Concetta Luna (Collection des universités de France). Paris.


The Beauty of the World in Plato’s Timaeus

Dominic O’Meara

Fribourg University, Switzerland

dominic.omeara@unifr.ch

Abstract: In the Timaeus Plato describes the world as the ‘most beautiful’ (kallistos, 29a5) of generated things. Perhaps indeed this is the first systematic description of the beauty of the world. It is, at any rate, one of the most influential statements of the theme. The Stoics were deeply convinced by it and later, in the third century A.D., at a time when contempt and hate for the world were propagated by Gnostic movements, Plotinus, interpreting the Timaeus, would write magnificent passages on the beauty and value of the world. But what does Plato mean by the ‘beauty’ of the world? What makes the world beautiful? In this paper these questions are approached first (1) by a brief discussion of the distinction which Plato appears to make in the Timaeus between beauty and the good. In one passage (Tim. 87c) ‘measure’ seems to relate to this distinction. It is suitable then (2) to look at a section of another late work of Plato, the Philebus, where the themes of beauty, goodness and measure may be compared in more detail. The theme of measure then takes us back (3) to the Timaeus, in order to examine the role played by measure, in particular mathematical measure, in constituting the beauty of the world. I discuss in detail the way in which mathematical structures make for the beauty of soul and body in the living whole that is the world.

Keywords: Aesthetics, Antiquity, harmony, the beautiful and the good, kalos kagathos.

*Versions of this paper were given first at Princeton University, on December 4, 2011, and then at Novosibirsk State University, on June 4, 2013, in the framework of the interdisciplinary seminar “ΤΕΧΝΗ. The Theoretical Foundations of Arts, Sciences and Technology in the Greco-Roman World” (supported by the Open Society Institute). I am grateful for the questions and comments that I received on these occasions, in particular the helpful remarks made by my commentator in Princeton, Professor Rachana Kamtaker.

In the Timaeus Plato describes the world as the ‘most beautiful’ (kallistos, 29a5) of generated things. Perhaps indeed this is the first systematic description of the beauty of the world. It is, at any rate, one of the most influential statements of the theme. The Stoics were deeply convinced by it0 and later, in the third century A.D., at a time when contempt and hate for the world were propagated by Gnostic movements, Plotinus, interpreting the Timaeus, would write magnificent passages on the beauty and value of the world.0

But what does Plato mean by the ‘beauty’ of the world? What makes the world beautiful? In this paper these questions will be approached first (1) by a brief discussion of the distinction which Plato appears to make in the Timaeus between beauty and the good.0 In one passage (Tim. 87c) ‘measure’ seems to relate to this distinction. It will be suitable then (2) to look at a section of another late work of Plato, the Philebus, where the themes of beauty, goodness and measure may be compared in more detail. The theme of measure will then take us back (3) to the Timaeus, in order to examine the role played by measure, in particular mathematical measure, in constituting the beauty of the world. I would like to discuss in detail the way in which mathematical structures make for the beauty of soul and body in the living whole that is the world.
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   ...   22

Похожие:

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconРоссийское философское сообщество и трансляция философского знания в XX веке
Б 24 Российское философское сообщество и трансляция философского знания в XX веке : моногр. / Н. Г. Баранец. – Ульяновск : УлГУ,...

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconЕ. А. Тоpчинов пути философии востока и запада: познание запредельного
Универсум самосовершенствования и упорядочения государства – конфуцианская традиция

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconВведение в астрологию
Высшая школа классической астрологии начинает беспрецедентный в истории российской астрологии проект – издание многотомного труда...

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconРабочая программа по дисциплине «Конфликтология» для специальности «связи с общественностью»
Тема Конфликты в современном обществе 8 Тема Социологическая традиция изучения конфликтов 9

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconЛекция Порождение реальности герменевтического пространства жизни...
Менталитет и традиция-предание

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconЛисты дневника
Великими Законами Космоса. Его очерки это размышления о прошлом, настоящем и будущем человечества. Философское наследие Н. К. Рериха...

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconКнига продолжает издание избранных произведений выдающегося нидерландского...
Составитель, переводчик и автор вступительной статьи Д. В. Сильвестров Научный комментарий Д. Э. Харитоновича

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconОткуда появилась такая традиция?
С одной стороны портфолио учителя необходимо администрациии образовательных учреждений для мониторинга эффективности работы преподавателя,...

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconГ, Порядком приема граждан на обучение по образовательным программам...
Настоящее Положение регулирует отношения по приему и отчислению граждан в муниципальное бюджетное общеобразовательное учреждение...

Философское антиковедение и классическая традиция iconАнкета-заявка 24мроч xlsx> Анкета-заявка на участие в Чтениях
Для участия в ключевых мероприятиях XXIV международных Рождественских образовательных чтениях «Традиция и новации: культура, общество,...

Вы можете разместить ссылку на наш сайт:


Все бланки и формы на filling-form.ru




При копировании материала укажите ссылку © 2019
контакты
filling-form.ru

Поиск